Skip to content

Abul Haytam

Abul Haytam

ABU’L-HAYṮAM AḤMAD B. ḤASAN GORGĀNĪ, Ismaʿili philosopher, for a long time one of the great unknown figures in the history of Irano-Islamic philosophy. A brief notice on him survives in the history of ʿAlī b. Zayd Bayhaqī (a notice in which the proper names are very badly treated in the Indian edition). The historian says: “I have never found any trace of him outside of a qaṣīda in Persian on which Moḥammad b. Sorḵ Nīšāpūrī commented.” And although he swears to not having seen, himself, any work of Abu’l-Hayṯam which would permit him to pass judgment on its scientific value, he classes him at the outset among the common philosophers (aʿwāmm-e falāsefa), i.e., “exoterists.” This is false. Abu’l-Hayṯam was an Ismaʿili philosopher, an esoterist (bāṭenī). Nāṣer-e Ḵosrow (d. between 465/1072 and 471/1078) reproaches him for having poorly posed the question of ebdāʿ (the primordial establishment of being) and relates that he was one of the adepts and friends of the ahl-e taʾyīd (those who receive heavenly assistance and inspiration); this term is characteristically used in Shiʿite vocabulary for designating the holy imams.

 

There is no doubt about the form of the complete name (given above) of master (Ḵᵛāǰa) Abu’l-Hayṯam. (He should not be confused with Ebn al-Hayṯam, the famous physician, astronomer, and mathematician, called Ptolemaeus Secundus, d. 430/1038.) He can be placed in the 4th/10th century, but not more precisely. His disciple and commentator, Moḥammad b. Sorḵ, in a vehement passage denounces the way in which Rūdakī (d. 329/940-41) and other Khorasani poets misinterpreted his thought. He would appear to be also contemporary with two other famous Ismaʿili thinkers, Moḥammad b. Aḥmad Naḵšabī (or Nasafī) and Abū Yaʿqūb Seǰestānī.

 

Apart from these scattered pieces of information, we know only what the commentators on his qaṣīda tell us about him and his work. Although they mention other works of his, unfortunately without listing the titles, only his qaṣīda (“ode” or canticum, as the term would have been translated in Medieval Latin) has come down to us. It is composed of abstruse questions and allusive figures of speech. Apparently the author had intended to respond to it himself. For one reason or another he did not do so; consequently, in order to understand the meaning of the qaṣīda and the importance of the questions posed, it is indispensable to read it in conjunction with one of the two important commentaries which have survived. These two Persian commentaries, edited only some twenty years ago, are extremely interesting in that they present two forms of Iranian Ismaʿili thought based on the same exemplary text.

 

One of these commentaries is the work of the celebrated Iranian Ismaʿili philosopher Nāṣer-e Ḵosrow. The text of the qaṣīda was communicated to him in 426/1069-70 by an Ismaʿili prince with whom he had established ties of friendship—the reigning sovereign of Badaḵšān, the amir ʿAlī b. al-Asad b. al-Ḥāreṯ. The prince had reconstructed the qaṣīda from memory and asked his friend to furnish the answers to the questions. Nāṣer-e Ḵosrow began on the work, which became one of the most important tracts presenting a comparative summa of Greek and Ismaʿili philosophy (Jāmeʿ al-ḥekmatayn). In the form that the amir transmitted it to him, the qaṣīda of Abu’l-Hayṯam contained eighty-two distichs (bayt), covering ninety-one questions: philosophical, logical, physical, grammatical, theosophic, and hermeneutic (taʾwīlī). In connection with each question, Nāṣer-e Ḵosrow, utilizing both the truths of Greek philosophy and those of Ismaʿili philosophy, inaugurated in Persian the discipline of comparative philosophy. The importance of Abu’l-Hayṯam is measured by the fact that his qaṣīda instigated this discipline.

 

The other commentary, earlier in the date, is the work not of a celebrated philosopher, but of an intellectual who has remained obscure up to now: Moḥammad b. Sorḵ (or Moḥammad-e Sorḵ, “Moḥammad the Red”), a direct disciple of the master, is mentioned in Bayhaqī’s notice and may be placed in the 4th-5th/10th-11th centuries. His object was not to attempt a comparative undertaking, as did Nāṣer-e Ḵosrow, but to furnish to the questions posed by the qaṣīda answers conforming to those his master would have given, had he completed the task. In fact, he answered only seventy-six questions, but these he answered very relevantly. To a certain extent, he acted as a mouthpiece for Abu’l-Hayṯam, who himself reveals the meaning of the qaṣīda. Moḥammad b. Sorḵ, who was an Ismaʿili (he speaks of ḵᵛāǰagān-e mā, “our masters,” and mardomān-e mā, “our co-religionists”), introduced his commentary with these words: “Master Abu’l-Hayṯam has composed a poem in which he has raised many questions. He did not, however, go as far as to formulate replies to them, since he left this world. That is why certain friends of mine entreated me, saying that it was my duty to formulate replies to these questions. That is what I have undertaken to do here with the aid of the Heavenly Helpers (ḵodāvandān-e taʾyīd, i.e., the holy imams) and of the friends of God (awlīā-ye Īzad).” In the final paragraph, he concludes: “Here are set down the replies to these questions. Everything that I have recorded here, I have read in the works of the wise men (ḥokamāʾ) and have written according to them. In addition, I was the disciple (šāgerdī kardam) of Master Abu’l-Hayṯam for nine years, and everything that I have recorded here, I have heard formulated by him; I have invented nothing of my own.” Thus he has set down in writing what could be set down (leaving, in the fashion of a good Ismaʿili esotericist, the opportunity for teaching orally which could not be set down).

 

We hear Abu’l-Hayṯam’s voice over and over again in the course of the commentary. For example, in connection with the difficulties posed by the theosophy of history: “Our master, Abu’l-Hayṯam, has expressly declared: ” For years I was preoccupied with this question. The people that I asked were such that I found them still more destitute of knowledge than myself. But so great was the problem, it pleased God to render it possible in my discourse and that is why I have spoken.”” The disciple had heard his master make this admission forty years before. Of the personal subjectivity which constitutes the “I” of the first person (manī-e man) he says: “Over and over I immersed myself in this problem, and questioned many people. No one was able to tell me on whom I could rely in this matter . . . Finally I asked Master Abu’l-Hayṯam the question.” In connection with the fundamental theologoumenon of the primordial beginning of existence (ebdāʿ) and its originator (mobdeʿ), the disciple states: “No one beside this eminent man treated the question.”

 

Thus the figure and work of Abu’l-Hayṯam emerge little by little. He ends his qaṣīda saying: “My object in posing all these questions has not at all been to vex the reader; I have posed them solely with the view to instruct.” Nāṣer-e Ḵosrow remarks, with a touch of bad temper, that it would have been still better to announce his project of answering them. That is which Abu’l-Hayṯam’s disciple had been forced to do, unbeknownst to him, before him. Consequently we have profited by two monuments of Ismaʿili thought which deal with its most characteristic points, such as taʾwīl (the hermeneutics of the spiritual meaning of the Koran) and the relation between the masters of Ismaʿili thought and the philosophers of the Hellenic tradition. The two commentaries ought to be examined simultaneously. The present author has drawn up a preliminary comparative outline dealing principally with the relation between Ismaʿilism and philosophy, the theosophy of nature, the reasons and the character of the Ismaʿili polemic against the great physician Rhazes (Moḥammad b. Zakarīyāʾ Rāzī, d. between 313/925 and 320/932), the notion of the “I”, angelology, astronomy, prophetology, etc. It is in proportion to and in direct measure with the progress made by Ismaʿili studies and those of Shiʿite philosophy in general that the importance of Abu’l-Hayṯam, one of the earliest philosopher-poets of Iran, will be specified.

 

Bibliography : ʿAlī b. Zayd Bayhaqī, Tatemma ṣewān al-ḥekma, ed. M. Šafīʿ, Lahore, 1935, p. 132, no. 8 of the Arabic; p. 91, no. 73 of the Persian (many faulty readings). A preliminary ed. of the qaṣīda alone was given by M. Mīnovī in Yādgār 8, pp. 9-21. Another edition with French tr. (without commentary) is found in Lazard, Premiers poètes. Nāṣer-e Ḵosrow, Kitâb-e Jâmiʿ al-Hikmatayn: Le Livre réunissant les deux Sagesses, ou Harmonie de la philosophie grecque et de la théosophie ismaélienne, Persian text ed. with French and Persian étude préliminaire by H. Corbin and M. Moʿīn (Bibliothèque Iranienne, Vol. 3),Tehran and Paris, 1953. Commentaire de la Qaṣîda d’Abû’l-Haiṯham Jorjânî attribué à Moḥammad ibn Sorkh de Nîshapour (IVe/Xe-Ve/XIe siècles), Persian text ed. with introduction and comparative summary in French by H. Corbin and M. Moʿīn (Bibliothèque Iranienne, Vol. 6), Tehran and Paris, 1955. W. Ivanow, Ismaili Literature, a Bibliographical Survey (The Ismaili Society Series A, no. 15), Tehran, 1963, p. 161, no. 751. H. Corbin, Histoire de la philosophie islamique I, Paris, 1964, pp. 115, 195.

H. Corbin

Originally Published: December 15, 1983